PMCCPMCCPMCC

Search tips
Search criteria 

Advanced

 
Logo of schbulOxford JournalsContact UsMy BasketMy AccountSchizophrenia BulletinAbout this JournalContact this JournalSubscriptionsCurrent IssueArchiveSearch
 
Schizophr Bull. 2006 January; 32(1): 47–68.
Published online 2005 October 19. doi:  10.1093/schbul/sbj012
PMCID: PMC2632189

Emerging Empirical Evidence on the Ethics of Schizophrenia Research

Abstract

Many challenging ethical questions come with the scientific efforts to understand the nature and treatment of schizophrenia. The empirical study of ethical aspects of schizophrenia research has sought to clarify and resolve many of these questions. In this article we provide an overview of the existing data-based literature on schizophrenia research ethics and outline directions for future inquiry. We examine 5 broad categories of inquiry into the ethics of schizophrenia research: (1) Scientific designs (eg, placebo-controlled studies and medication-free intervals, prodromal and high-risk research, and genetics research); (2) informed consent and decision-making capacity, including assessment of decisional abilities, as well as intervention studies; (3) understanding and perceptions of risk and benefit (including the therapeutic misconception); (4) influences on research participation (including voluntarism, altruism, and other motivations); and (5) key participant safeguards, such as protocol review and participant advocates. We discuss how empirical work in each of these areas answers certain questions and raises new ones. Finally, we highlight important gaps in our understanding of ethically relevant aspects of schizophrenia research and offer a specific research agenda for empirical ethics.

Keywords: schizophrenia, bioethics, clinical trials, decision-making capacity, informed consent, empirical studies

Introduction

The personal suffering and public health consequences of schizophrenia create a societal need—many would say an ethical imperative—to perform scientific studies on its etiology, treatment, and prevention.1–9 The importance of research on schizophrenia is especially great in light of the international burden of the disease.10–14 Moreover, current treatments, while beneficial, provide only symptomatic relief, may be difficult to tolerate, and often do not restore premorbid levels of functioning.15–17 In addition, many treatment approaches lack adequate empirical support.18–21

Although these realities urge further research, the specific nature of this serious illness22 has raised concerns about the potential vulnerability of research participants with schizophrenia.5,23–25 For reasons of scientific validity,26 the research needed to help those diagnosed with schizophrenia must recruit people who are actually affected by the disorder. This, in turn, has raised important questions about the ethical conduct of schizophrenia research.27–36 Sincere and thoughtful individuals hold different opinions on recruitment strategies, acceptable risks, appropriate safeguards, and other questions, while federal regulatory standards (such as the “Common Rule”)37 do not offer specific guidance on many controversial issues.33,38–40 (See Fischer,40 in this issue, for a comprehensive review of important historical documents in the field of research ethics.) The empirical study of ethical aspects of schizophrenia research has therefore sought to clarify and resolve many of these disagreements.32,34,41,42

Consequently, schizophrenia research ethics has grown dramatically over the past decade, fueled by the collaborative efforts of multidisciplinary investigators, the receptiveness of editors to publish novel and early developmental work, and most important, the commitment of resources to the study of research ethics by the MacArthur Foundation, the National Institutes of Health, the National Alliance for Research on Schizophrenia and Depression, the Greenwall Foundation, the Alzheimer's Association, and others. Prominent themes in this revitalized literature include constructive approaches to the ethical dilemmas of certain scientific designs, research participants' strengths and vulnerabilities related to informed consent and decision-making capacity, attitudes toward clinical research and influences on research participation, protocol review, and broader considerations of scientific integrity in mental health research.5,24,25,43–49 In this article we provide an overview of data-based publications in schizophrenia research ethics and outline possible directions for additional inquiry. It is our hope that this review will help characterize the strengths and gaps in the field, inspiring future inquiry and creating a context for understanding the array of empirical and conceptual manuscripts featured in this special issue of Schizophrenia Bulletin.

Diverse Scientific Designs and Procedures

Diverse study designs are necessary to resolve the varied scientific questions about schizophrenia that remain. Protocols that incorporate placebo comparisons, randomization, “blinding,” and medication-free intervals help to determine the impact of pharmacologic interventions.50–53 Epidemiological approaches examine the association between putative etiological factors, such as infection and famine, and the later emergence of schizophrenia.54–57 Symptom provocation helps to examine and model illness-phenomena and their correlates.58 Studies with people identified as “at risk” for the development of schizophrenia, such as prospective prodromal and genetic studies, help to establish biological and psychosocial vulnerabilities, sources of resilience, and other disease features.59,60 Such widely differing protocols require varying procedures and combinations of procedures. These may range from gathering and analyzing de-identified data from national databases to withholding medications, administering new pharmacological agents, conducting neuroimaging studies, performing in-depth structured interviews, drawing blood, or providing psychotherapy.61–65 Other examples exist as well, ranging from large multicenter phase 4 clinical trials to health economics and services studies, each of which differs because of the hypotheses being tested.66,67

Four predominant ethics issues arise from these designs and procedures.29,30,68–72 First is the issue of whether novel intervention studies (especially those that are prolonged) compare new medicines with placebo, standard treatments, or “treatment as usual.”68,73,74 This is a particular concern in studies where standard or usual treatments offer symptomatic improvement but are of uncertain effectiveness because of imperfect prior research.35 Researchers may consequently turn to placebo controls, finding it difficult to satisfy obligations to research subjects to offer “comparable” treatments, when scientific equipoise on the effectiveness of those treatments has not yet been established.75–77 The second issue pertains to whether the risks associated with an individual project are appropriate, eg, no single risk is excessive in proportion to the nature of the illness, the risk-benefit ratio is acceptable in light of the aims of the work, and the psychosocial and biological risks are well described.25,52,78,79 Objections to these kinds of risks are often raised in studies using medication-free intervals or symptom provocation.29,80,81 The third issue is whether sufficient safeguards protect participants from research risks.33,78,82 For instance, do research volunteers truly understand the nature of the risks they are undertaking, and do institutional review board (IRB) members perform adequate oversight of more burdensome and nontherapeutic studies? Should capacity be routinely reevaluated during the course of these kinds of studies?83,84 Finally, are certain designs or procedures unacceptable under all or specific circumstances, perhaps for reasons related to societal values?69 Although subjects may wish to take on certain risks, do human rights or community concerns trump their decision?35,85,86

Empirical evidence has helped to address some of these ethical concerns (see Table 1). Consider, for example, the ethics of medication-free intervals and placebo comparisons in schizophrenia. Moser and colleagues recently reported on 10 patients whose antipsychotic medications were withdrawn as part of a medication washout phase.87 Although the patients' reasoning scores did decline, MacArthur Competence Assessment Tool for Clinical Research (MacCAT-CR) Understanding and Appreciation subscale scores remained stable from before medication withdrawal until the 2-week retest (ie, still during the medication-free interval).87 This study suggests that some participants may retain decisional abilities even when their antipsychotic medication is stopped, although further work is necessary to replicate this small study.

Table 1.
Scientific Designs and Procedures

Roberts et al. have also provided relevant data on medication-free periods in research.88,89 They asked patients diagnosed with schizophrenia about the level of risk associated with a medication washout, finding that the respondents assigned “moderate risk” to this procedure. This was significantly more than having a physical examination and significantly less than a spinal tap or taking a “dangerous new medication.”89 In this study, willingness to participate in a protocol was inversely related, and appropriate, to participants' perceptions of study risk. It should be noted, however, that participants were given only brief descriptions of these research procedures (as opposed to a complete study consent form), and their understanding of the procedures was not assessed. Thus, more work is needed to clarify how understanding of procedures, in the context of a study as a whole, may affect perceived risks or willingness to participate.

In an earlier project, Roberts et al. had asked people with schizophrenia and psychiatrists for their views of a hypothetical clinical trial in which a study participant experienced symptom reemergence during a washout. Unexpectedly, the majority of patients and doctors recommended giving the ill study participant medication against his wishes to gain symptomatic relief and recover earlier levels of functioning.88 This suggested a more paternalistic attitude than might otherwise be expected from these respondents.

Related concerns about medication-free intervals stem from the possibility of lasting harm from symptom reemergence, although there is no conclusive evidence that harm occurs.90 Meta-analyses of placebo-controlled studies in schizophrenia have not definitively demonstrated an increased risk of suicidality among subjects receiving placebos,91,92 as once feared.68 Issues around the exclusion of suicidal patients from clinical trials are explored cogently in the article by Wilson and Stanley (in this issue).84 Taken together, these findings underscore the need for further empirical work to respond to the concerns of participants, families, communities, clinicians, and investigators.

Similarly, empirical ethics researchers can provide more data for understanding the ethical dimensions of prodromal and first-episode schizophrenia research.93–96 Corcoran recently provided a comprehensive review of the ethical issues pertinent to prodromal research,96 highlighting psychosocial risks such as stigmatization and loss of confidentiality. Additionally, the manner in which investigators define the new prodromal entities (see Wilson and Stanley,84 in this issue) and the ways that subjects weigh the actual risks of early intervention against the potential risk of future illness remain important as well. Variation in rates of “conversion” to psychosis in clinical studies, as discussed in the article by Haroun and colleagues in this issue,97 further complicates risk and benefit assessments. Empirical work examining the perspectives of first-episode individuals and their families,93 the risks for noncompliance, and understanding of potential risks and benefits is now being conducted, while others have begun to apply the MacCAT model to capacity assessments among prodromal and first-episode subjects.98–101

Currently, some of the most rapid progress in psychiatric research comes from studies that examine genetic vulnerability, interactions of genetic and environmental factors on disease expression, the role of endophenotypes, and genetic and genomic determinants of treatment response.102–110 However, the ethical considerations of these genetic studies have seldom been evaluated using empirical ethics methods. In a unique early study Roberts et al. asked people with schizophrenia their perception of risk associated with a general blood draw versus a blood draw for genetic information.89 The respondents did not assign greater risk to the genetic test, apparently focusing solely on the minimal biological risk associated with venipuncture. This is another area where empirical ethics can be useful in describing the ethical landscape.

Specific ethical considerations for genetics research endeavors arise from the personal, social, financial, and occupational consequences (intended or not) of the quest for greater genetic information.111,112 What are the implications for insurability, schooling, and employment? How are people's childbearing decisions affected? How well do people understand the complex information they receive? How much information should be provided, and what are the best educational approaches for providing it? What protections can and should be implemented to protect private information? What are nonenrolled relatives entitled to learn? There is some preliminary evidence on the views of nonschizophrenia populations regarding genetic research, but more work is needed in schizophrenia, just as in other major neuropsychiatric illnesses.111,113–116

Given the immense potential impact of genetic information, empirical ethicists cannot afford to ignore the personal, familial, societal, and policy aspects of psychiatric genetic and genomic research.117–119 Although investigators are currently advised not to offer research participants data from their own test results (on the grounds that the data do not meet standards for clinical utility or “reasonable medical certainty”),120 the time will come when genetic data may be interpretable at an individual or family level. As this point nears, personal and social ethical considerations will become increasingly pressing.121,122

Evidence regarding other scientific designs and procedures is lacking as well. For instance, very few studies have examined ethical issues related to different phases of multicenter clinical trials, neuroimaging, crossover designs, sequential research projects, and symptom provocation by biological interventions (eg, intravenous agents or disturbing visual images to trigger trauma-related responses and symptoms).

As we seek to understand the ethical issues associated with these designs, it will be important to assess and integrate the views of patient-participants, as well as other stakeholders, like families and clinicians. Early work comparing these perspectives has already yielded interesting and unexpected results.88,123 Risks associated with different kinds of research and procedures are seen differently by participants, clinicians, and different subject populations.88,123–125 As highlighted by the large online survey presented in this issue by Muroff and colleagues,126 psychiatric research may be stigmatized in the eyes of the general public—in particular, the notion that people with psychiatric disorders may lack capacity to consent appeared to drive the more restrictive views of respondents toward psychiatric research compared with research on medical disorders. This important finding should raise awareness among investigators and reviewers, indicating the need to be attuned to ongoing stigma toward psychiatric research.

Finally, a relatively unexplored question concerns how best to perform ethics research itself.42 Issues such as what sort of threshold for capacity to consent should be required for studies on capacity to consent (see Saks, Palmer, and Dunn,127 in this issue), the relevance of therapeutic misconception for adequacy of consent (see Miller and Wendler,42 in this issue), and deception in ethics-related research, for example, require further elucidation.128

Decision-Making Capacity and Informed Consent

Descriptive Studies

An early and ongoing focus of empirical ethics work has been the assessment of decision-making capacity. It is important to note that, prior to the application of empirical methods to study consent-related abilities of people with psychiatric disorders, a common perception was that people with serious psychiatric disorders, such as schizophrenia and depression, were incompetent to consent to research.129 In the 1980s and 1990s numerous studies began to examine this view more rigorously. (Although beyond the scope of this article to review these in detail, excellent reviews of these early studies are available.45,130) In addition, investigators began to examine consent procedures themselves, suspecting that difficulties with informed consent resided at least partially in those procedures and not just in characteristics or symptoms of the patients. Intriguing results emerged from these early studies, including findings that (1) many consent forms and disclosures were inadequate, but even with improved disclosures, many patients continued to have difficulty understanding research;129 (2) many participants in research did not understand randomization and double-blind procedures and seemed to believe that the research was conducted for their personal benefit;129,131,132 (3) cognitive symptoms, conceptual disorganization, and acute psychosis were related to decision-making abilities;133–136 and (4) patients with neuropsychiatric disorders showed both heterogeneity, as well as strengths, in informed consent contexts (relating both to research and treatment).134–139

The highly innovative multiyear, multisite MacArthur competency study, which laid much of the groundwork for inquiry into decisional abilities, was the largest systematic study of capacity to consent.134–136 It operationalized the concepts of understanding, appreciation, reasoning, and expression of choice into semistructured interview instruments and used them to evaluate decisional abilities of people with schizophrenia or schizoaffective disorder, major depression, ischemic heart disease, and healthy control subjects matched for each diagnostic group (total N = 498).134–136 The schizophrenia and depression groups manifested worse understanding, appreciation, and reasoning compared with the control groups, and the schizophrenia subjects were more likely to score in the impaired range (defined as a level of performance that would include fewer than 5% of the community controls) compared with the patients with depression and heart disease.135 Appelbaum et al. have since described the research strengths of subjects with moderate depression,140 findings supported by Stiles et al. in their work.141 And as we note below (and see Table 3), people with schizophrenia show strong responses to education on the consent process.

Table 3.
Intervention Studies: Informed Consent in Schizophrenia

Nonetheless, a key finding, borne out by subsequent research, was that subjects with schizophrenia showed substantial heterogeneity in their performance, and many (48%) were not impaired on any of the 3 main measures.135 Furthermore, impairment on one scale was not predictive of impairment on the others, indicating that individuals could vary not just from one another, but also from scale to scale. Finally, test-retest findings indicated that changes in symptoms appeared to relate to changes in decisional abilities, supporting the notion that decisional abilities are not static traits but fluctuate with changes in other important factors.134

The original instruments were lengthy and, while suited to the important and specific task of characterizing the abilities of these populations, were not subsequently adopted for more than a few other studies.142,143 Appelbaum and Grisso themselves—the developers of the instruments—emphasized that they were not appropriate or designed for routine clinical use.144 However, the instruments were later adapted into shorter versions, evolving into the now widely used MacArthur Competence Assessment Tools for Treatment (MacCAT-T)145 and Clinical Research (MacCAT-CR).146

The MacArthur study was critical not only for collecting valuable data but also for highlighting the development of shared methods like well-validated assessment instruments. Numerous studies utilizing the MacCAT-T and MacCAT-CR have been conducted to date, many of which are reviewed here (also see Dunn et al.147 for a review of these and other decision-making assessment tools). As with the assessment of any complex human task, however, it is unlikely that any one tool will be the ultimate authority in evaluating decision-making capacity. Thus, post-MacArthur, the continued development, refinement, and validation of tools for assessing capacity remain important for empirical ethics.44,147,148

Another focus of evidence-based ethics researchers has been the effect of psychiatric symptoms on decisional abilities, particularly relative to other influences such as cognition. Early work pointed to the mixed role of psychotic symptoms in decisional impairment. For example, before, during, and after MacArthur,133,135,149 conceptual disorganization (as measured with the Brief Psychiatric Rating Scale150) was found to be correlated with impaired understanding of treatment disclosures among schizophrenia patients. In more recent studies using the MacCAT-CR and other measures of decisional abilities, psychotic symptoms have not been as strongly or consistently associated with decisional abilities as cognitive functioning (Table 2).148,151–155

Table 2.
Decision-Making Abilities of People With Schizophrenia and Related Disorders

Much of the recent research on decision-making capacity addresses whether, when, and to what degree people with serious mental illnesses are able to consent to research. The debate over these questions was fueled in large part by the 1998 report of the National Bioethics Advisory Commission, Research Involving Persons With Mental Disorders That May Affect Decision-Making Capacity.28 This report, although intended to facilitate additional protections for people with mental disorders, itself became a focus of debate because it did not give adequate weight to what was already known about decisional capacity (ie, the heterogeneity of decision-making capacity among people with mental illness).5,130,156,157 It also seemed to single out psychiatric illness for special protections, when, in fact, many medical disorders and demographic variables (eg, lower education) appear to place people at greater risk.156,158,159 The report was never approved by the federal government, in part due to these concerns. Indeed, the growing body of evidence (much of which is cited here) suggests that while people with schizophrenia are more vulnerable to impaired capacity, “psychiatric patients and psychiatric research are fundamentally similar to medical patients and medical research, respectively.”5(p1428) Nevertheless, the report represented a watershed event for empirical ethics research in schizophrenia. It invigorated investigators to characterize more comprehensively the decisional abilities of people with psychiatric disorders and to devise and test methods for improving the consent process.

This body of work underscores that people with schizophrenia, while at risk for impairments relative to healthy comparison groups, should not be categorically viewed as having impaired capacity because many perform as well as their non-ill counterparts. This point, as well as the heterogeneity of performance of schizophrenia patients (as evidenced by larger standard deviations on measures of decisional abilities compared with normal comparison groups) is emphasized in the analysis provided in this issue by Jeste, Depp, and Palmer160 and by Appelbaum's review.44 As we have noted above, the collected data also indicate that cognitive impairments, rather than psychopathology, may represent the greatest threat to informed decision making.33,44,151,153,155,161

Areas in need of further study related to decision-making capacity for schizophrenia research are highlighted in several other articles in this issue.44,162 Kim emphasizes, in a valuable conceptual piece, that translating the accumulated data on decisional abilities into categorical capacity determinations has proved challenging.162 Nevertheless, he asserts, if the field strives to inform policymaking, then this line of inquiry needs to be vigorously pursued. Given that IRBs are becoming more prone to require capacity assessments and explicit statements and justification from investigators about how capacity will be determined (as Appelbaum points out in this issue),44 this area of research gains even more practical urgency for investigators. Other areas in need of further exploration include development and validation of brief screening tools for the identification of people at risk of impaired capacity (see, eg, Appelbaum's review in this issue),44,148 and investigating the ethical aspects, correlates, and complicated implications of other forms of capacity, such as financial capacity (for a thorough review of this neglected ethical topic, see Marson and Phillips,163 in this issue).

Intervention Studies

Given the findings of early decision-making studies in schizophrenia, an important next effort was to improve subject decision making. This would help optimize abilities to consent to both research and treatment. These studies (summarized in Table 3) present an encouraging picture: with thoughtful efforts aimed at providing an educational consent process, most people with schizophrenia can perform adequately on decision-making assessments. In studies using a variety of educational methods, the mean performance of patients rose to the same level as that of healthy comparison subjects.83,141,151,164

Several unanswered questions remain, however. First, it is still not clear, despite numerous positive studies, what constitutes the active element of these interventions. Is it the method of education or the enriched social interaction that makes the difference in consent enhancement? Most studies did not attempt to control for this possibility (eg, with an enhanced social element in the control condition), nor did they generally report the comparability of time spent in each consent condition. Thus, more emphasis is needed on disentangling various aspects of the consent process.

Moreover, have any of these findings been translated into actual practice? Empirical ethics researchers must take the next step of enhancing real-world research practices. Participation on IRBs, consultation to research review systems, and insistence on the evidence-based standards now available will help assure that the valuable work conducted to date fulfills its promise of improving the ethical foundations of research. Such efforts can enhance the experiences of and protections for the volunteers who make these scientific endeavors possible.

Understanding/Perceptions of Risk and the Therapeutic Misconception

Understanding/Perceptions of Risk

All prospective research participants are expected to understand and weigh the risks of a research protocol prior to making their decision. For psychiatry researchers it is consequently important to know whether subjects understand risks adequately, whether they judge risks like nonpsychiatrically ill individuals do, and how these judgments affect their participation. There is a growing body of literature on this topic among people with schizophrenia (Table 4).

Table 4.
Understanding/Perceptions of Research Risks and the Therapeutic Misconception

This work suggests several conclusions, as well as the need for further investigation. First, people with schizophrenia have been found to be sensitive to the special risks involved in the controversial designs described earlier. Specifically, they recognize heightened risks associated with washout and medication-free intervals.88,123 Moreover, patients are able to discern meaningfully among different, hypothetical research protocols of varying levels of potential harm.123 In that study of decisions about washout and placebo control, patients' ratings of risk frequently differed from those of psychiatrists: patients rated the scenarios as more harmful. Roberts's team also found that willingness to participate was inversely associated with perceptions of research risks.88,123,165 Similarly, Hummer and colleagues indicate that concerns about potential risks associated with a placebo-controlled trial were a disincentive to participate for over half the patients surveyed.166

In some cases, efforts to inform participants about the risks of specific protocols appear to need more work. For example, in a relatively low-risk protocol, researchers found that, compared with healthy controls, middle-aged and older patients with schizophrenia had more difficulty responding to an open-ended question about the potential risks of enrolling.167 In this same study it was found that a computer-based, enhanced consent procedure was associated with better performance on the question.167

Further studies will be needed to clarify the dimensions of nonbiological risk (eg, psychosocial, economic, anxiety-related) that are associated with taking part in psychosocial or survey research.47,96,168,169 In biologically oriented research as well, the phenomenon of “respondent burden” (eg, time, energy, and emotional expenditures by participants) has received only passing interest. As defined recently by Ulrich and colleagues,170(p17) “respondent burden” can be viewed as “a subjective phenomenon that describes the perception by the subject of the psychological, physical, and/or economic hardships associated with participation in the research process.” Perspectives of patients, family members, clinicians, investigators, and reviewers should be sought on the risks and burdens of existing and emerging forms of research, including “respondent burden.” Other forms of risk that have not been thoroughly elucidated have been dubbed “bystander risk”86—namely, the biological and nonbiological risks to nonsubjects. These types of risks have been more commonly described in research on sexually transmitted diseases and genetics, but examples in psychiatric protocols have also been cited.86 Legal, psychological, and privacy-related risks of research can also accrue to bystanders; more work is needed both conceptually and empirically to clarify the types and impact of these risks and to develop guidelines for investigators and reviewers in analyzing and safeguarding against them.

Therapeutic Misconception

Related to the focus on understanding and perception of research risks is the conceptualization of potential benefit in research. Appelbaum and colleagues have forged an intriguing line of research that seeks to uncover potential misconceptions among both participants and investigators. The foremost of these misconceptions, the inappropriate confusion or conflation of research methods and goals with those of usual clinical care, has been termed “the therapeutic misconception.”131 This misconception leads to an unrealistic or inappropriate expectation of personal benefit or individualized care. A number of authors in this issue discuss the relevance of the therapeutic misconception to the ethical basis of schizophrenia research.42,171–173

Since the initial description of the therapeutic misconception in 1982,131 investigators and commentators have been concerned and puzzled about this problematic—and possibly quite prevalent—aspect of research participation.174 Although the initial misconception studies involved patients who were participating in psychiatric research, the phenomenon has since been described in many nonpsychiatric research populations.175–180 The true prevalence and risk factors for therapeutic misconception remain elusive, however, in part because consensus has not yet emerged on what beliefs or statements truly constitute it.181 Moreover, whether evidence of therapeutic misconception should invalidate informed consent or invoke extra protections also requires clarification.42,182

Several relevant studies have now been completed, although more work is needed to identify specific vulnerabilities and to develop interventions designed to address them. Ideally, future studies will use shared methods (including validated measures of the therapeutic misconception and its effects), allowing results to be compared meaningfully.

Among those studies already completed, the largest investigated the therapeutic misconception in a wide variety of research protocols. Lidz, Appelbaum, and colleagues183 employed extensive interviews with 225 subjects enrolling in 44 research trials (ranging from phase 1 cancer chemotherapy trials to other phase 3 and 4 trials). They examined beliefs about research participation, risks and benefits, and differences between research and usual care. Nearly a third of research participants appeared to hold inaccurate beliefs regarding the degree of individualization of their treatment (termed “TM1”). Approximately one-half of participants held unreasonable beliefs regarding the nature or likelihood of benefit (deemed unreasonable based on the specific study in which they were enrolling and called “TM2”). Over 60% of participants manifested a therapeutic misconception judging by one or both of these criteria.183,184 Older age, lower education, and worse self-described health placed people at risk for holding a therapeutic misconception.

In a study of people with schizophrenia, Dunn and colleagues used a brief, 6-item questionnaire asking about TM1-related beliefs within a hypothetical, placebo-controlled, clinical trial.185 Of 87 patients with schizophrenia or schizoaffective disorder, approximately two-thirds answered at least 1 question incorrectly. However, nearly one-third answered all items correctly, suggesting that many participants are able to distinguish the sometimes subtle differences of research from usual care.

Performance on this particular measure of therapeutic misconception was correlated with MacCAT-CR performance and with neuropsychological functioning, but not with psychopathology. In Candilis and colleagues' report (in this issue), the authors also found that some respondents did not seem to grasp the inherent uncertainty of the scientific method, believing that they would “get a better treatment.”172 However, differentiating the therapeutic misconception from hope and trust in one's doctor remains an elusive yet necessary aspect of ethics research.

In a semistructured interview study of people with schizophrenia, Roberts et al. have found that respondents consistently indicate that research of varying kinds offers greater benefit “to society” than to individual participants (unpublished data). This suggests that some schizophrenia research volunteers may indeed have an intellectual understanding of the overall goals of research. A cautionary note, however, is that participants in this study erroneously ascribed benefit to individual study volunteers enrolled in “toxicity” studies, indicating that people with schizophrenia may not understand all types of protocols without specific consent processes to support their understanding.

These findings all point to the need, expressed for a number of years, for brief, targeted efforts to address the therapeutic misconception. Educating research participants about key distinctions between research and usual care are essential to these efforts.132,174 Because these distinctions will depend on the unique characteristics of a given protocol, efforts should be made to develop educational interventions tailored to specific types of studies (eg, pharmacologic, psychosocial, genetic).

Influences on Research Participation

Voluntarism

Informed consent encompasses not only the provision of relevant information and the presence of decision-making capacity but also voluntariness.186 As articulated in The Belmont Report, voluntariness in research participation “requires conditions free of coercion and undue influence.”186 Operationalizing these broad requirements has proved more challenging. Compared to the conceptual and empirical work on information disclosure and decision-making capacity, voluntarism has received relatively little attention until recently (Table 5).187,188

Table 5.
Influences on Research Participation

Like other concerns about psychiatric research, those related to voluntarism arise from worries about the abilities of people with mental illness to exercise their autonomy. Can subjects identify and enact their genuine preferences in the face of serious symptoms and difficult life circumstances? Some fear that these challenges—though not unique to psychiatric syndromes—may lead to increased vulnerability or perceptions of pressure to participate. These concerns have not been adequately investigated using empirical methods.187,189,190

Several recent articles have attempted to address this void in more detail. Roberts, for example, offered a conceptual model of voluntarism189 that employs a positive operationalization. In this view, voluntarism may comprise 4 components—including authenticity based in one's own circumstances, history, clarity, intentionality, and coherence with one's values. Roberts's outline of 4 domains that contribute to voluntarism (developmental; illness-related; psychological, cultural, and religious; and external features and pressures) provides a starting point for inquiry: which elements, for example, affect the decision about whether to participate, and which affect the entire experience of participation?

Nelson and Merz parsed voluntariness slightly differently (although the same fundamental domains articulated by Roberts are apparent in their model).187,189 Their model describes potential influences on voluntariness arising from the characteristics of research subjects, including capacity, socioeconomic factors, and other role- or illness-related factors. It also details potential researcher- and setting-related factors. These include 3 forms of influence initially described by Faden and Beauchamp, ie, persuasion, manipulation, and coercion.191 As Nelson and Merz emphasize, our knowledge of the prevalence of any of these influences is limited because of the paucity of research.

In research examining the genetics of psychiatric disorders, voluntarism takes on a previously unstudied dimension—the effect of family and its role. Families can affect participation decisions, ongoing study involvement, and poststudy information sharing.192 These aspects of voluntarism (which seem to fall into several of the domains outlined by Roberts) have also not been studied adequately. Work in other fields (notably the genetics of breast cancer and Huntington's disease)193–195 can be informative, but it is not necessarily descriptive of the experience of persons with mental illness.

Motivations for Participation in Research

People with schizophrenia report several positive motivations for their decisions to enroll in research projects. Similar to other research populations, patients with schizophrenia endorse the scientific, social, psychological, and compensation-related benefits of participation.165,196 A series of semistructured interview studies by Roberts et al. have documented that people with schizophrenia express altruistic attitudes pertaining to research. They seek to help society, to help science, to help others with the illness (now and in the future), and to help foster hope.196,197 People with schizophrenia cite a number of other factors that influence their reasons for participating in research.165,196,198–200 For instance, approximately half of a sample of participants with schizophrenia who were interviewed in depth about their motivations cited biological need.165

Although limited data exist regarding the differences between individuals who do and do not agree to participate in research—in part, because it is difficult to conduct these kinds of studies—the data that do exist tend to support the notion that patients with schizophrenia are fundamentally similar to patients with medical illnesses.172,198,199,201,202 For example, Candilis and colleagues' novel work on this issue indicates that patients with schizophrenia and schizoaffective disorder provide a combination of socially directed and personally motivated reasons for research participation. Because this hypothetical study related to an antibiotic trial, rather than a trial of antipsychotic medication, it would be interesting to learn more about motivations for participation decisions related specifically to psychiatric trials, particularly as risks escalate.

There is also little data examining the role of financial incentives to participate in research. For years, concerns have been expressed about the potentially coercive effects of monetary payments, although others have tried to allay these concerns.203–207 Yet the few empirical studies that have been conducted (in nonpsychiatric patients) do not clearly indicate that monetary payments lead potential research subjects to ignore risk.202,208 Similarly, Candilis et al. found that the role of monetary compensation for a hypothetical antibiotic trial seemed to be minimal for most participants.172 By contrast, Roberts et al. found that monetary compensation was given greater weight than doctors' and family recommendations by people who were considering hypothetical medication-free and placebo-control schizophrenia protocols.88,123 These findings point to the need for further study of how potential participants balance various influences. Studying the effects of financial and other types of compensation, in combination with and relative to other potential influences on decision making in actual, not just hypothetical, research contexts, would be particularly valuable.190

Gaining a better understanding of the motivations and barriers to research participation is valuable for all clinical research. Scientific implications fuel this area of empirical ethics research as well, as enrollment of nonrepresentative samples is a threat to external validity.26 In view of such concerns, Halpern has proposed a novel method for eliciting the views and preferences of potential enrollees.209 This method, called “prospective preference assessment,” involves polling potential participants (eligible for a planned trial) prior to the formal recruitment process. Barriers to recruitment could be identified and the design modified if indicated. Differences between those who would or would not enroll could also be assessed. This strategy, which can be adapted to schizophrenia research, could easily be evaluated for its effect on efficiency of recruitment and enrollment and on the composition of resulting participant pools.

Key Safeguards: Protocol Review and Participant Advocates

Human research employs many safeguards, some of which—like informed consent, conflict of interest management, confidentiality protections, and institutional review board oversight—are federally regulated. Others—like scientific review processes, debriefing methods, and publication processes—are not. Most of these topics, with the exception of informed consent, have received relatively little attention in empirical studies. As a result, little is known; much remains to be explored. Protocol review by IRBs, ongoing protocol monitoring, and participant debriefing are less scrutinized dimensions of schizophrenia research (Table 6). Because these have a strong influence on the design and conduct of protocols, it is problematic that we do not know more about how they occur and how they affect the research experiences of participants. (The commentary provided in this issue by Shore reflects the need for greater exploration of such issues as participant debriefing, the use of sliding scale risk-benefit assessments, and the use of consent monitors.173)

Table 6.
Participant Safeguards

The IRB review process, while critical to any study, is itself not well understood or characterized. Only a few studies have been conducted examining the work of IRBs, with most data coming from general descriptions of IRB members or analysis of consent forms and applications.210–212 Data on the risk-benefit assessments or other review criteria used by IRB members are far less plentiful.213,214 Despite the ongoing discussions about risk, and the need to protect potentially “vulnerable” groups, minimal data exist about how IRBs actually arrive at their complex decisions.215,216 IRBs take on the extraordinary challenge of reviewing myriad protocols involving patients with medical and neuropsychiatric disorders, yet there is almost no guidance about how to define terms such as “vulnerability,”33 how to determine whether investigators have provided protections adequate to the risks of a study, and how to identify adequate group decision making.

Recently, Shah and colleagues at the National Institutes of Health Department of Clinical Bioethics identified variable risk assessments among IRB chairs reviewing pediatric protocols—assessments whose interpretation of risk often ran counter to “available data on risks and [federal] regulations themselves.”217(p476) Others have described the variability among IRBs when they assess the benefits of clinical research.218

For psychiatry in particular, there are many unanswered questions: how do review board members assess risks of psychiatric protocols as opposed to those from other specialties? What factors (eg, protocol-related, reviewer-related, investigator-related) influence the process and outcome of these reviews? Does the review process itself differ for psychiatric and nonpsychiatric protocols, and if so, in what ways? Does variability in interpretation of federal standards affect the assignment of protections to psychiatric subjects?

A large landmark survey of IRB members, chairs, and investigators at 491 IRBs did not explicitly examine differences in level or effectiveness of oversight among different types of protocols (eg, for psychiatric versus medical protocols). The findings, published in 1998 and known as the Bell Report,210 suggested that overall, those involved in the system of IRB oversight felt it was functioning efficiently and protecting participants' welfare. On the other hand, several urgent findings, as well as recommendations made by the Office of the Inspector General that same year,219 have yet to be adequately resolved.220

For example, the Bell survey found notable differences between high-volume and low-volume IRBs in workload and time spent reviewing protocols.210 It would be useful to examine what influence such differences have on the review process at different institutions. It also appeared that IRBs focused heavily on consent forms, with 60% of chairs reporting that the most frequent concern about consent forms had to do with overly technical language. Despite this finding and recent work confirming ongoing problems with consent form language,221 meaningful modifications to promote better comprehension have yet to be adopted. In schizophrenia research specifically, we know little about the internal workings of the review and monitoring process for these protocols relative to others.

As noted above, evidence from the pediatric literature suggests substantial variability in how IRBs interpret the language of federal regulations.37 In Shah et al.'s survey of IRB chairs, for example, investigators found that a lumbar puncture received lower mean risk ratings when the research subject was ill rather than healthy.217 Thus, it is possible that some reviewers vary the “minimal risk” standard depending on the health status of the subject. In contrast, some commentators suggest that the definition of minimal risk should be measured against risks ordinarily encountered by healthy persons.222

In psychiatric research, data on differential risk assessment is available from a recent study by Roberts and colleagues. The authors examined psychiatrists' and schizophrenia patients' perceptions of the level of risk of a number of research procedures. Each procedure was described separately, not as part of an overall study, so that procedures could be compared to one another (Roberts et al., in press).89 Participants rated the risks relative to everyday risks encountered by people with schizophrenia.

Psychiatrists and patients rated many of the procedures as having similar levels of risk, but patients rated several scenarios (eg, symptom induction, lumbar puncture, and 2-week medication discontinuation) as more risky than psychiatrists. These findings raise several points in need of further study: patients may be more attuned to risk than they are often given credit for. Conversely, researchers and review board members may rate risks differently from their subjects. Might this difference have significant effects on the protections required for psychiatric research? Without more extensive data, subjects, communities, and reviewers will not be able to conduct consistent review or construct coherent policy.130,223

Another safeguard, the use of subject or participant advocates, has only recently been studied empirically (see Stroup, Bredthauer, and Appelbaum,224 in this issue). This process is designed to safeguard participants who may lack decisional capacity during enrollment in a clinical trial, or who may subsequently lose capacity. In its recommendations the National Bioethics Advisory Commission (NBAC) relied on the use of an ill-defined “legally authorized representative (LAR)” for consent to certain procedures (ie, minimal risk or greater than minimal risk with the prospect of direct benefit). But NBAC would only allow an LAR to enroll an incapable subject if the subject had previously provided authorization. This would require an uncommon degree of prescience on the part of patients and investigators. Leaving aside for the moment the difficulties of determining “minimal” risk and the “prospect” of direct medical benefit, the use of the subject advocate contains many layers of subtlety that have been insufficiently studied, from the standards of capacity assessment to the timing and procedures of surrogate involvement. The work of Stroup and colleagues is therefore highly informative, as it is the first empirical study of subject advocate procedures actually enacted for schizophrenia research.

Conclusion

Although it is not possible to touch on every conceivable area of research ethics in schizophrenia, we have attempted to survey the landscape of recent and emerging findings. Built on the foundation of early studies conducted by pioneers in empirical ethics (whose work is well represented in this issue of Schizophrenia Bulletin),42,44,84,163 recent conceptual and empirical work has begun to tackle important questions. These endeavors include exploring the dimensional and categorical aspects of decision-making capacity, detailing the correlates of decision-making capacity, making inroads into enhancing informed consent procedures, bringing forth the previously unheard voices and perspectives of patient-participants themselves, and highlighting the varied needs of participants, families, and their communities.

As schizophrenia research expands and advances in new directions—many of which will bring novel and unexpected ethical challenges—the diverse and vital field of empirical ethics can only improve the collaboration between patients, communities, and researchers. As Table 7 highlights, much remains to be done. We hope that this review informs and stimulates the discussion and future work needed to advance the field.

Table 7.
Ethical Issues in Schizophrenia Research: Research Agenda

Acknowledgments

The authors gratefully acknowledge the National Institute of Mental Health for support for Drs. Dunn (MH66062), Roberts (MH01918), and Candilis (MH01851). The contents of this article are solely the responsibility of the authors and do not necessarily represent the official views of the National Institute of Mental Health. Dr. Dunn also wishes to thank the National Association for Research on Schizophrenia and Depression and the Greenwall Foundation for their support. Dr. Roberts also wishes to express her appreciation to the National Association for Research on Schizophrenia and Depression and the National Institute on Drug Abuse. The authors wish to thank Ms. Deannah Neal and Ms. Krisy Edenharder for their technical assistance with this manuscript.

References

1. Knapp M, Mangalore R, Simon J. The global costs of schizophrenia. Schizophr Bull. 2004;30:279–293. [PubMed]
2. Uhl GR, Grow RW. The burden of complex genetics in brain disorders. Arch Gen Psychiatry. 2004;61:223–229. [PubMed]
3. Cole JO. Research barriers in psychopharmacology. Am J Psychiatry. 1977;134:896–898. [PubMed]
4. Eichelman B, Wikler D, Hartwig A. Ethics and psychiatric research: problems and justification. Am J Psychiatry. 1984;141:400–405. [PubMed]
5. Michels R. Are research ethics bad for our mental health? N Engl J Med. 1999;340:1427–1430. [PubMed]
6. Miller FG, Fins JJ. Protecting vulnerable research subjects without unduly constraining neuropsychiatric research. Arch Gen Psychiatry. 1999;56:701–702. [PubMed]
7. Hyman SE. Protecting patients, preserving progress: ethics in mental health illness research. Acad Med. 1999;74:258–259. [PubMed]
8. The Campaign for Mental Health Reform. Emergency Response: A Roadmap for Federal Action on America's Mental Health Crisis. National Alliance for the Mentally Ill; July 2005.
9. US Department of Health and Human Services. Mental Health: A Report of the Surgeon General—Executive Summary. Washington, DC: US Dept of Health and Human Services, Substance Abuse and Mental Health Services Administration, Center for Mental Health Services, National Institutes of Health, National Institute of Mental Health; 1999.
10. World Health Organization. World Health Report 2001—Mental Health: New Understanding, New Hope. World Health Organization; 2001.
11. Robins LN, Locke BZ, Regier DA. An overview of psychiatric disorders in America. In: Robins LN, Regier DA, editors. Psychiatric Disorders in America: The Epidemiologic Catchment Area Study. New York: Free Press; 1991.
12. Kendler KS, Gallagher TJ, Abelson JM, Kessler RC. Lifetime prevalence, demographic risk factors, and diagnostic validity of nonaffective psychosis as assessed in a US community sample: the National Comorbidity Survey. Arch Gen Psychiatry. 1996;53:1022–1031. [PubMed]
13. Sartorius N, Jablensky A, Korten A, et al. Early manifestations and first-contact incidence of schizophrenia in different cultures: a preliminary report on the initial evaluation phase of the WHO Collaborative Study on determinants of outcome of severe mental disorders. Psychol Med. 1986;16:909–928. [PubMed]
14. Jablensky A, Sartorius N, Ernberg G, et al. Schizophrenia: manifestations, incidence and course in different cultures: a World Health Organization ten-country study. Psychol Med Monogr Suppl. 1992;20:1–97. [PubMed]
15. Conley RR, Kelly DL. Management of treatment resistance in schizophrenia. Biol Psychiatry. 2001;50:898–911. [PubMed]
16. Fenton WS, Blyler CR, Heinssen RK. Determinants of medication compliance in schizophrenia: empirical and clinical findings. Schizophr Bull. 1997;23:637–651. [PubMed]
17. Andrews G, Sanderson K, Corry J, Issakidis C, Lapsley H. Cost-effectiveness of current and optimal treatment for schizophrenia. Br J Psychiatry. 2003;183:427–435. [PubMed]
18. Stahl SM, Grady MM. A critical review of atypical antipsychotic utilization: comparing monotherapy with polypharmacy and augmentation. Curr Med Chem. 2004;11:313–327. [PubMed]
19. Remington GJ, Prendergast P, Bezchlibnyk-Butler KZ. Neuroleptic dosing in chronic schizophrenia: a 10-year follow-up. Can J Psychiatry. 1997;42:53–57. [PubMed]
20. Fayek M, Flowers C, Signorelli D, Simpson G. Psychopharmacology: underuse of evidence-based treatments in psychiatry. Psychiatr Serv. 2003;54:1453–1454. 1456. [PubMed]
21. Valenstein M, Copeland L, Owen R, Blow F, Visnic S. Delays in adopting evidence-based dosages of conventional antipsychotics. Psychiatr Serv. 2001;52:1242–1244. [PubMed]
22. Mueser KT, McGurk SR. Schizophrenia. Lancet. 2004;363:2063–2072. [PubMed]
23. Capron AM. Ethical and human-rights issues in research on mental disorders that may affect decision-making capacity. N Engl J Med. 1999;340:1430–1434. [PubMed]
24. Pinals DA, Appelbaum PS. The history and current status of competence and informed consent in psychiatric research. Isr J Psychiatry Relat Sci. 2000;37:82–94. [PubMed]
25. Carpenter WT, Conley RR. Sense and nonsense: an essay on schizophrenia research ethics. Schizophr Res. 1999;35:219–225. [PubMed]
26. Emanuel EJ, Wendler D, Grady C. What makes clinical research ethical? JAMA. 2000;283:2701–2711. [PubMed]
27. Hilts PJ. Psychiatric researchers under fire. New York Times. 1998 May 19;:F1. F5. [PubMed]
28. National Bioethics Advisory Commission. Research Involving Persons With Mental Disorders That May Affect Decision-Making Capacity. Rockville, Md: National Bioethics Advisory Commission; 1998.
29. Carpenter WT, Schooler NR, Kane JM. The rationale and ethics of medication-free research in schizophrenia. Arch Gen Psychiatry. 1997;54:401–407. [PubMed]
30. Miller FG. Placebo-controlled trials in psychiatric research: an ethical perspective. Biol Psychiatry. 2000;47:707–716. [PubMed]
31. Roberts LW, Geppert CM, Brody JL. A framework for considering the ethical aspects of psychiatric research protocols. Compr Psychiatry. 2001;42:351–363. [PubMed]
32. Roberts LW. Ethics and mental illness research. Psychiatr Clin North Am. 2002;25:525–545. [PubMed]
33. Rosenstein DL, Miller FG. Ethical considerations in psychopharmacological research involving decisionally impaired subjects. Psychopharmacology (Berl) 2003;171:92–97. [PubMed]
34. Frank E, Novick DM, Kupfer DJ. Beyond the question of placebo controls: ethical issues in psychopharmacological drug studies. Psychopharmacology. 2003;171:19–26. [PubMed]
35. Carpenter WT, Appelbaum PS, Levine RJ. The Declaration of Helsinki and clinical trials: a focus on placebo-controlled trials in schizophrenia. Am J Psychiatry. 2003;160:356–362. [PubMed]
36. Charney DS. The National Bioethics Advisory Commission report: the response of the psychiatric research community is critical to restoring public trust. Arch Gen Psychiatry. 1999;56:699–700. [PubMed]
37. Department of Health and Human Services, National Institutes of Health, Office of Protection from Research Risks. Code of Federal Regulations, Title 45: Public Welfare. Part 46, Subpart AProtection of Human Subjects. Bethesda, Md: Dept of Health and Human Services; 1991.
38. Karlawish JH. Clinical value: the neglected axis in the system of research ethics. Account Res. 1999;7:255–264. [PubMed]
39. Michels R. Research on persons with impaired decision making and the public trust. Am J Psychiatry. 2004;161:777–779. [PubMed]
40. Fischer BA. A summary of important documents in the field of research ethics. Schizophr Bull. In press. [PMC free article] [PubMed]
41. Stanley BH, Stanley M. Psychiatric patients in research: protecting their autonomy. Compr Psychiatry. 1981;22:420–427. [PubMed]
42. Miller FG, Wendler D. The relevance of empirical research for bioethics. Schizophr Bull. In press. [PMC free article] [PubMed]
43. Appelbaum PS. Involving decisionally impaired subjects in research: the need for legislation. Am J Geriatr Psychiatry. 2002;10:120–124. [PubMed]
44. Appelbaum PS. Decisional capacity of patients with schizophrenia to consent to research: taking stock. Schizophr Bull. In press. [PMC free article] [PubMed]
45. Roberts LW. The ethical basis of psychiatric research: conceptual issues and empirical findings. Compr Psychiatry. 1998;39:99–110. [PubMed]
46. Roberts LW, Hammond KA, Warner TD, Lewis R. Influence of ethical safeguards on research participation: comparison of perspectives of people with schizophrenia and psychiatrists. Am J Psychiatry. 2004;161:2309–2311. [PubMed]
47. Dunn LB, Roberts LW. Emerging findings in ethics of schizophrenia research. Curr Opin Psychiatry. 2005;18:111–119. [PubMed]
48. Kim SY, Appelbaum PS, Jeste DV, Olin JT. Proxy and surrogate consent in geriatric neuropsychiatric research: update and recommendations. Am J Psychiatry. 2004;161:797–806. [PubMed]
49. Kim SY, Millard RW, Nisbet P, Cox C, Caine ED. Potential research participants' views regarding researcher and institutional financial conflicts of interest. J Med Ethics. 2004;30:73–79. [PMC free article] [PubMed]
50. Dawkins K, Lieberman JA, Lebowitz BD, Hsiao JK. Antipsychotics: past and future: National Institute of Mental Health Division of Services and Intervention Research Workshop, July 14, 1998. Schizophr Bull. 1999;25:395–405. [PubMed]
51. Lima AR, Bacalcthuk J, Barnes TR, Soares-Weiser K. Central action beta-blockers versus placebo for neuroleptic-induced acute akathisia. Cochrane Database Syst Rev. 2004 CD001946. [PubMed]
52. Gaebel W, Moller HJ, Buchkremer G, et al. Pharmacological long-term treatment strategies in first episode schizophrenia—study design and preliminary results of an ongoing RCT within the German Research Network on Schizophrenia. Eur Arch Psychiatry Clin Neurosci. 2004;254:129–140. [PubMed]
53. Jayaram MB, Hosalli P. Risperidone versus olanzapine for schizophrenia. Cochrane Database Syst Rev. 2005 CD005237. [PubMed]
54. Brown AS, Begg MD, Gravenstein S, et al. Serologic evidence of prenatal influenza in the etiology of schizophrenia. Arch Gen Psychiatry. 2004;61:774–780. [PubMed]
55. Brown AS, Schaefer CA, Quesenberry CP, Jr, Liu L, Babulas VP, Susser ES. Maternal exposure to toxoplasmosis and risk of schizophrenia in adult offspring. Am J Psychiatry. 2005;162:767–773. [PubMed]
56. St Clair D, Xu M, Wang P, et al. Rates of adult schizophrenia following prenatal exposure to the Chinese famine of 1959–1961. JAMA. 2005;294:557–562. [PubMed]
57. Neugebauer R. Accumulating evidence for prenatal nutritional origins of mental disorders. JAMA. 2005;294:621–623. [PubMed]
58. Carpenter WT. The schizophrenia ketamine challenge study debate. Biol Psychiatry. 1999;46:1081–1091. [PubMed]
59. Phillips LJ, McGorry PD, Yung AR, McGlashan TH, Cornblatt B, Klosterkotter J. Prepsychotic phase of schizophrenia and related disorders: recent progress and future opportunities. Br J Psychiatry Suppl. 2005;48:s33–44. [PubMed]
60. Stone WS, Faraone SV, Seidman LJ, Olson EA, Tsuang MT. Searching for the liability to schizophrenia: concepts and methods underlying genetic high-risk studies of adolescents. J Child Adolesc Psychopharmacol. 2005;15:403–417. [PubMed]
61. Hawton K, Sutton L, Haw C, Sinclair J, Deeks JJ. Schizophrenia and suicide: systematic review of risk factors. Br J Psychiatry. 2005;187:9–20. [PubMed]
62. Davis CE, Jeste DV, Eyler LT. Review of longitudinal functional neuroimaging studies of drug treatments in patients with schizophrenia. Schizophr Res. 2005;78:45–60. [PubMed]
63. Buchanan RW, Davis M, Goff D, et al. A summary of the FDA-NIMH-MATRICS workshop on clinical trial design for neurocognitive drugs for schizophrenia. Schizophr Bull. 2005;31:5–19. [PubMed]
64. Vauth R, Corrigan PW, Clauss M, et al. Cognitive strategies versus self-management skills as adjunct to vocational rehabilitation. Schizophr Bull. 2005;31:55–66. [PubMed]
65. Jones C, Cormac I, Silveira da Mota Neto JI, Campbell C. Cognitive behavior therapy for schizophrenia. Cochrane Database Syst Rev. 2004;18 CD000524.
66. Drummond MF, Knapp MR, Burns TP, Shadwell P. Issues in the design of studies for the economic evaluation of new atypical antipsychotics: the ESTO study. J Ment Health Policy Econ. 1998;1:15–22. [PubMed]
67. Hamann J, Leucht S, Kissling W. Are the second-generation antipsychotics cost-effective? A critical review on the background of different health systems. Pharmacopsychiatry. 2003;36:18–26. [PubMed]
68. Fleischhacker WW, Czobor P, Hummer M, Kemmler G, Kohnen R, Volavka J. Placebo or active control trials of antipsychotic drugs? Arch Gen Psychiatry. 2003;60:458–464. [PubMed]
69. Kim SY. Benefits and burdens of placebos in psychiatric research. Psychopharmacology. 2003;171:13–18. [PubMed]
70. Weijer C. Placebo-controlled trials in schizophrenia: are they ethical? are they necessary? Schizophr Res. 1999;35:211–218. [PubMed]
71. Lavori PW. Placebo control groups in randomized treatment trials: a statistician's perspective. Biol Psychiatry. 2000;47:717–723. [PubMed]
72. Emanuel EJ, Miller FG. The ethics of placebo-controlled trials—a middle ground. N Engl J Med. 2001;345:915–919. [PubMed]
73. Miller AL, Crismon ML, Rush AJ, et al. The Texas medication algorithm project: clinical results for schizophrenia. Schizophr Bull. 2004;30:627–647. [PubMed]
74. Rush AJ, Crismon ML, Kashner TM, et al. Texas Medication Algorithm Project, phase 3 (TMAP-3): rationale and study design. J Clin Psychiatry. 2003;64:357–369. [PubMed]
75. Geddes J. Generating evidence to inform policy and practice: the example of the second generation “atypical” antipsychotics. Schizophr Bull. 2003;29:105–114. [PubMed]
76. Miller PB, Weijer C. Rehabilitating equipoise. Kennedy Inst Ethics J. 2003;13:93–118. [PubMed]
77. World Medical Association. Declaration of Helsinki: Ethical Principles for Medical Research Involving Human Subjects. Helsinki, Finland; 1964. [PubMed]
78. Weijer C, Miller PB. When are research risks reasonable in relation to anticipated benefits? Nat Med. 2004;10:570–573. [PubMed]
79. Alphs L, Anand R, Islam MZ, et al. The international suicide prevention trial (interSePT): rationale and design of a trial comparing the relative ability of clozapine and olanzapine to reduce suicidal behavior in schizophrenia and schizoaffective patients. Schizophr Bull. 2004;30:577–586. [PubMed]
80. D'Souza D, Berman R, Krystal J, Charney DS. Symptom provocation studies in psychiatric disorders: scientific value, risks and future. Biol Psychiatry. 1999;46:1060–1080. [PubMed]
81. Rosenstein DL. IRB review of psychiatric medication discontinuation and symptom-provoking studies. Biol Psychiatry. 1999;46:1039–1043. [PubMed]
82. Shore D. Ethical principles and informed consent: an NIMH perspective. Psychopharmacol Bull. 1996;32:7–10. [PubMed]
83. Moser DR, Reese R, Hey C, Schultz S, Arndt S, Beglinger L, Duff K, Andreasen N. Using a brief intervention to improve decisional capacity in schizophrenia research. Schizophr Bull. In press. [PMC free article] [PubMed]
84. Wilson ST, Stanley B. Ethical concerns in schizophrenia research. Schizophr Bull. In press. [PMC free article] [PubMed]
85. DeGrazia D. Ethical issues in early-intervention clinical trials involving minors at risk for schizophrenia. Schizophr Res. 2001;51:77–86. [PubMed]
86. Kimmelman J. Medical research, risk, and bystanders. IRB. 2005;27:1–6. [PubMed]
87. Moser D, Reese R, Schultz S, et al. Informed consent in medication-free schizophrenia research. Am J Psychiatry. 2005;162:1209–1211. [PubMed]
88. Roberts LW, Warner TD, Nguyen KP, Geppert CM, Rogers MK, Roberts BB. Schizophrenia patients' and psychiatrists' perspectives on ethical aspects of symptom re-emergence during psychopharmacological research participation. Psychopharmacology (Berl) 2003;171:58–67. [PubMed]
89. Roberts LW, Green Hammond KA, Hoop J. An inverse relationship between perceived harm and participation willingness in schizophrenia research protocols. Am J Psychiatry. In review. [PubMed]
90. Carpenter WT., Jr The risk of medication-free research. Schizophr Bull. 1997;23:11–18. [PubMed]
91. Khan A, Khan SR, Leventhal RM, Brown WA. Symptom reduction and suicide risk among patients treated with placebo in antipsychotic clinical trials: an analysis of the Food and Drug Administration database. Am J Psychiatry. 2001;158:1449–1454. [PubMed]
92. Storosum JG, van Zwieten BJ, Wohlfarth T, de Haan L, Khan A, van den Brink W. Suicide risk in placebo vs active treatment in placebo-controlled trials for schizophrenia. Arch Gen Psychiatry. 2003;60:365–368. [PubMed]
93. McGlashan TH. Psychosis treatment prior to psychosis onset: ethical issues. Schizophr Res. 2001;51:47–54. [PubMed]
94. Heinssen RK, Perkins DO, Appelbaum PS, Fenton WS. Informed Consent in Early Psychosis Research: National Institute of Mental Health workshop, November 15, 2000. Schizophr Bull. 2001;27:571–583. [PubMed]
95. Candilis PJ. Early intervention in schizophrenia: three frameworks for guiding ethical inquiry. Psychopharmacology (Berl) 2003;171:75–80. [PubMed]
96. Corcoran C, Malaspina D, Hercher L. Prodromal interventions for schizophrenia vulnerability: the risks of being “at risk.” Schizophr Res. 2005;73:173–184. [PMC free article] [PubMed]
97. Haroun N, Dunn LB, Haroun A, Cadenhead KS. Risk and protection in prodromal schizophrenia: ethical implications for clinical practice and future research. Schizophr Bull. In press. [PMC free article] [PubMed]
98. Lauber C, Rossler W. Relatives and their attitude to early detection of schizophrenic psychosis. Psychiatr Bull R Coll Psychiatr. 2003;27:134–136.
99. Kampman O, Laippala P, Vaananen J, et al. Indicators of medication compliance in first-episode psychosis. Psychiatry Res. 2002;110:39–48. [PubMed]
100. O'Toole MS, Ohlsen RI, Taylor TM, Purvis R, Walters J, Pilowsky LS. Treating first episode psychosis—the service users' perspective: a focus group evaluation. J Psychiatr Ment Health Nurs. 2004;11:319–326. [PubMed]
101. Schaffner KF, McGorry PD. Preventing severe mental illnesses: new prospects and ethical challenges. Schizophr Res. 2001;51:3–15. [PubMed]
102. Bierut LJ, Schuckit MA, Hesselbrock V, Reich T. Co-occurring risk factors for alcohol dependence and habitual smoking. Alcohol Res Health. 2000;24:233–241. [PubMed]
103. Lyons-Warren A, Chang JJ, Balkissoon R, et al. Evidence of association between bipolar disorder and Citron on chromosome 12q24. Mol Psychiatry. 2005;10:807–809. [PubMed]
104. Wilffert B, Zaal R, Brouwers JR. Pharmacogenetics as a tool in the therapy of schizophrenia. Pharm World Sci. 2005;27:20–30. [PubMed]
105. Malhotra AK, Murphy GM, Jr, Kennedy JL. Pharmacogenetics of psychotropic drug response. Am J Psychiatry. 2004;161:780–796. [PubMed]
106. Maier W, Hofgen B, Zobel A, Rietschel M. Genetic models of schizophrenia and bipolar disorder: overlapping inheritance or discrete genotypes? Eur Arch Psychiatry Clin Neurosci. 2005;255:159–166. [PubMed]
107. Payne JL, Potash JB, DePaulo JR., Jr Recent findings on the genetic basis of bipolar disorder. Psychiatr Clin North Am. 2005;28:481–498. [PubMed]
108. Craddock N, O'Donovan MC, Owen MJ. The genetics of schizophrenia and bipolar disorder: dissecting psychosis. J Med Genet. 2005;42:193–204. [PMC free article] [PubMed]
109. Cowan WM, Kopnisky KL, Hyman SE. The human genome project and its impact on psychiatry. Annu Rev Neurosci. 2002;25:1–50. [PubMed]
110. Kendler KS, Kuhn JW, Vittum J, Prescott CA, Riley B. The interaction of stressful life events and a serotonin transporter polymorphism in the prediction of episodes of major depression: a replication. Arch Gen Psychiatry. 2005;62:529–535. [PubMed]
111. Biesecker BB, Peay HL. Ethical issues in psychiatric genetics research: points to consider. Psychopharmacology (Berl) 2003;171:27–35. [PubMed]
112. Geppert CM. The Stamp of Sorrow: Ethical and Religious Aspects of Psychiatric Genetics. Garden Grove, Calif: International Reform University; 2001.
113. Smith LB, Sapers B, Reus VI, Freimer NB. Attitudes towards bipolar disorder and predictive genetic testing among patients and providers. J Med Genet. 1996;33:544–549. [PMC free article] [PubMed]
114. Jones I, Scourfield J, McCandless F, Craddock N. Attitudes towards future testing for bipolar disorder susceptibility genes: a preliminary investigation. J Affect Disord. 2002;71:189–193. [PubMed]
115. Roberts LW, Warner TD, Geppert CM, Rogers M, Hammond KAG. Employees' perspectives on ethically important aspects of genetics research participation: a pilot study. Compr Psychiatry. 2005;46:27–33. [PubMed]
116. Roberts LW, Geppert CM, Warner TD. Perspectives on use and protection of genetic information in work settings: results of a preliminary study. Soc Sci Med. 2005;60:1855–1858. [PubMed]
117. Issa AM. Ethical considerations in clinical pharmacogenomics research. Trends Pharmacol Sci. 2000;21:247–249. [PubMed]
118. Yeh M, Morley KI, Hall WD. The policy and ethical implications of genetic research on attention deficit hyperactivity disorder. Aust N Z J Psychiatry. 2004;38:10–19. [PubMed]
119. Tsuang DW, Faraone SV, Tsuang MT. Genetic counseling for psychiatric disorders. Curr Psychiatry Rep. 2001;3:138–143. [PubMed]
120. Shore D, Berg K, Wynne D, Folstein MF. Legal and ethical issues in psychiatric genetic research. Am J Med Genet. 1993;48:17–21. [PubMed]
121. Morley KI, Hall WD, Carter L. Genetic screening for susceptibility to depression: can we and should we? Aust N Z J Psychiatry. 2004;38:73–80. [PubMed]
122. Appelbaum PS. Ethical issues in psychiatric genetics. J Psychiatr Pract. 2004;10:343–351. [PubMed]
123. Roberts LW, Warner TD, Brody JL, Roberts B, Lauriello J, Lyketsos C. Patient and psychiatrist ratings of hypothetical schizophrenia research protocols: assessment of harm potential and factors influencing participation decisions. Am J Psychiatry. 2002;159:573–584. [PubMed]
124. Annett RD, Brody JL, Scherer DG, Perkett EA. Perception of risk associated with asthma research procedures among adolescents, parents, and pediatricians. J Allergy Clin Immunol. 2004;114:1138–1145. [PubMed]
125. Brody JL, Scherer DG, Annett RD, Pearson-Bish M. Voluntary assent in biomedical research with adolescents: a comparison of parent and adolescent views. Ethics Behav. 2003;13:79–95. [PubMed]
126. Muroff JR, Hoerauf SL, Kim SYH. Is psychiatric research stigmatized? an experimental survey of the public. Schizophr Bull. In press. [PMC free article] [PubMed]
127. Saks ER, Palmer BW, Dunn LB. Meta-consent in research on decisional capacity: a “Catch-22”? Schizophr Bull. In press. [PMC free article] [PubMed]
128. Miller FG, Wendler D. Assessing the ethics of ethics research: a case study. IRB. 2004;26:9–12. [PubMed]
129. Benson PR, Roth LH, Winslade WJ. Informed consent in psychiatric research: preliminary findings from an ongoing investigation. Soc Sci Med. 1985;20:1331–1341. [PubMed]
130. Roberts L, Roberts B. Psychiatric research ethics: an overview of evolving guidelines and current ethical dilemmas in the study of mental illness. Biol Psychiatry. 1999;46:1025–1038. [PubMed]
131. Appelbaum PS, Roth LH, Lidz C. The therapeutic misconception: informed consent in psychiatric research. Int J Law Psychiatry. 1982;5:319–329. [PubMed]
132. Appelbaum PS, Roth LH, Lidz CW, Benson P, Winslade W. False hopes and best data: consent to research and the therapeutic misconception. Hastings Cent Rep. 1987;17:20–24. [PubMed]
133. Schachter D, Kleinman I, Prendergast P, Remington G, Schertzer S. The effect of psychopathology on the ability of schizophrenic patients to give informed consent. J Nerv Ment Dis. 1994;182:360–362. [PubMed]
134. Grisso T, Appelbaum PS, Mulvey EP, Fletcher K. The MacArthur Treatment Competence Study. II: measures of abilities related to competence to consent to treatment. Law Hum Behav. 1995;19:127–148. [PubMed]
135. Grisso T, Appelbaum PS. The MacArthur Treatment Competence Study. III: abilities of patients to consent to psychiatric and medical treatments. Law Hum Behav. 1995;19:149–174. [PubMed]
136. Appelbaum PS, Grisso T. The MacArthur Treatment Competence Study. I: mental illness and competence to consent to treatment. Law Hum Behav. 1995;19:105–126. [PubMed]
137. Soskis DA. Schizophrenic and medical inpatients as informed drug consumers. Arch Gen Psychiatry. 1978;35:645–647. [PubMed]
138. Stanley B, Stanley M, Lautin A, Kane J, Schwartz N. Preliminary findings on psychiatric patients as research participants: a population at risk? Am J Psychiatry. 1981;138:669–671. [PubMed]
139. Kleinman I, Schachter D, Jeffries J, Goldhamer P. Effectiveness of two methods for informing schizophrenic patients about neuroleptic medication. Hosp Community Psychiatry. 1993;44:1189–1191. [PubMed]
140. Appelbaum PS, Grisso T, Frank E, O'Donnell S, Kupfer DJ. Competence of depressed patients for consent to research. Am J Psychiatry. 1999;156:1380–1384. [PubMed]
141. Stiles PG, Poythress NG, Hall A, Falkenbach D, Williams R. Improving understanding of research consent disclosures among persons with mental illness. Psychiatr Serv. 2001;52:780–785. [PubMed]
142. Pruchno RA, Smyer MA, Rose MS, Hartman-Stein PE, Henderson-Laribee DL. Competence of long-term care residents to participate in decisions about their medical care: a brief, objective assessment. Gerontologist. 1995;35:622–629. [PubMed]
143. Dellasega C, Frank L, Smyer M. Medical decision-making capacity in elderly hospitalized patients. J Ethics Law Aging. 1996;2:65–74. [PubMed]
144. Grisso T, Appelbaum PS. Values and limits of the MacArthur Treatment Competence Study. Psychol Public Policy Law. 1996;2:167–181.
145. Grisso T, Appelbaum PS, Hill-Fotouhi C. The MacCAT-T: a clinical tool to assess patients' capacities to make treatment decisions. Psychiatr Serv. 1997;48:1415–1419. [PubMed]
146. Appelbaum PS, Grisso T. MacCAT-CR: MacArthur Competence Assessment Tool for Clinical Research. Sarasota, Fla: Professional Resource Press; 2001.
147. Dunn LB, Nowrangi M, Palmer BW, Jeste DV, Saks E. Assessing capacity to consent to treatment and research: a review of instruments. Am J Psychiatry. In press.
148. Palmer BW, Dunn LB, Appelbaum PS, et al. Assessment of capacity to consent to research among older persons with schizophrenia, Alzheimer disease, or diabetes mellitus: comparison of a 3-item questionnaire with a comprehensive standardized capacity instrument. Arch Gen Psychiatry. 2005;62:726–733. [PubMed]
149. Grisso T, Appelbaum PS. Mentally ill and non-mentally-ill patients' abilities to understand informed consent disclosures for medication: preliminary data. Law Hum Behav. 1991;15:377–388. [PubMed]
150. Overall J, Gorham D. The Brief Psychiatric Rating Scale. Psychol Rep. 1962;10:799–812.
151. Carpenter WT, Gold JM, Lahti AC, et al. Decisional capacity for informed consent in schizophrenia research. Arch Gen Psychiatry. 2000;57:533–538. [PubMed]
152. Moser DJ, Schultz SK, Arndt S, et al. Capacity to provide informed consent for participation in schizophrenia and HIV research. Am J Psychiatry. 2002;159:1201–1207. [PubMed]
153. Kovnick JA, Appelbaum PS, Hoge SK, Leadbetter RA. Competence to consent to research among long-stay inpatients with chronic schizophrenia. Psychiatr Serv. 2003;54:1247–1252. [PubMed]
154. Saks ER, Dunn LB, Marshall BJ, Nayak GV, Golshan S, Jeste DV. The California Scale of Appreciation: a new instrument to measure the appreciation component of capacity to consent to research. Am J Geriatr Psychiatry. 2002;10:166–174. [PubMed]
155. Wirshing DA, Wirshing WC, Marder SR, Liberman RP, Mintz J. Informed consent: assessment of comprehension. Am J Psychiatry. 1998;155:1508–1511. [PubMed]
156. Dunn LB, Jeste DV. Enhancing informed consent for research and treatment. Neuropsychopharmacology. 2001;24:595–607. [PubMed]
157. Oldham JM, Haimowitz S, Delano SJ. Protection of persons with mental disorders from research risk: a response to the report of the National Bioethics Advisory Commission. Arch Gen Psychiatry. 1999;56:688–693. [PubMed]
158. Sugarman J, McCrory DC, Hubal RC. Getting meaningful informed consent from older adults: a structured literature review of empirical research. J Am Geriatr Soc. 1998;46:517–524. [PubMed]
159. Casarett DJ, Karlawish JH, Hirschman KB. Identifying ambulatory cancer patients at risk of impaired capacity to consent to research. J Pain Symptom Manage. 2003;26:615–624. [PubMed]
160. Jeste DV, Depp CA, Palmer BW. Magnitude of impairment in decisional capacity in people with schizophrenia compared to normal subjects: an overview. Schizophr Bull. In press. [PMC free article] [PubMed]
161. Palmer BW, Dunn LB, Appelbaum PS, Jeste DV. Correlates of treatment-related decision-making capacity among middle-aged and older patients with schizophrenia. Arch Gen Psychiatry. 2004;61:230–236. [PubMed]
162. Kim SYH. When does decisional impairment become decisional incompetence? ethical and methodological issues in capacity research in schizophrenia. Schizophr Bull. In press. [PMC free article] [PubMed]
163. Marson DC, Phillips J. Financial capacity in persons with schizophrenia and severe mental illness: clinical and ethical aspects. Schizophr Bull. In press. [PMC free article] [PubMed]
164. Dunn LB, Lindamer LA, Palmer BW, Golshan S, Schneiderman LJ, Jeste DV. Improving understanding of research consent in middle-aged and elderly patients with psychotic disorders. Am J Geriatr Psychiatry. 2002;10:142–150. [PubMed]
165. Kaminsky A, Roberts LW, Brody JL. Influences upon willingness to participate in schizophrenia research: an analysis of narrative data from 63 people with schizophrenia. Ethics Behav. 2003;13:279–302. [PubMed]
166. Hummer M, Holzmeister R, Kemmler G, et al. Attitudes of patients with schizophrenia toward placebo-controlled clinical trials. J Clin Psychiatry. 2003;64:277–281. [PubMed]
167. Dunn LB, Jeste DV. Problem areas in the understanding of informed consent for research: study of middle-aged and older patients with psychotic disorders. Psychopharmacology (Berl) 2003;171:81–85. [PubMed]
168. Saks ER, Jeste DV, Granholm E, Palmer BW, Schneiderman L. Ethical issues in psychosocial interventions research involving controls. Ethics Behav. 2002;12:87–101. [PubMed]
169. Sieber JE, Baluyot RM. A survey of IRB concerns about social and behavioral research. IRB. 1992;14:9–10. [PubMed]
170. Ulrich CM, Wallen GR, Feister A, Grady C. Respondent burden in clinical research: when are we asking too much of subjects? IRB. 2005;27:17–20. [PubMed]
171. Dunn LB, Palmer BW, Keehan MK. Understanding of placebo controls among older people with schizophrenia. Schizophr Bull. In press. [PMC free article] [PubMed]
172. Candilis PJ, Geppert CM, Fletcher KE, Lidz CW, Appelbaum PS. Willingness of subjects with thought disorder to participate in research: reasoning and correlations to decision-making capacity, psychosis, and demographics. Schizophr Bull. In press. [PMC free article] [PubMed]
173. Shore D. Ethical issues in schizophrenia research. Schizophr Bull. In press. [PMC free article] [PubMed]
174. Lidz CW, Appelbaum PS. The therapeutic misconception: problems and solutions. Med Care. 2002;40:V55–63. [PubMed]
175. Advisory Committee on Human Radiation Experiments. The Human Radiation Experiments. New York: Oxford University Press; 1996.
176. Daugherty C, Ratain MJ, Grochowski E, et al. Perceptions of cancer patients and their physicians involved in phase I trials. J Clin Oncol. 1995;13:1062–1072. [PubMed]
177. Rodenhuis S, van den Heuvel WJ, Annyas AA, Koops HS, Sleijfer DT, Mulder NH. Patient motivation and informed consent in a phase I study of an anticancer agent. Eur J Cancer Clin Oncol. 1984;20:457–462. [PubMed]
178. Penman DT, Holland JC, Bahna GF, et al. Informed consent for investigational chemotherapy: patients' and physicians' perceptions. J Clin Oncol. 1984;2:849–855. [PubMed]
179. Llewellyn-Thomas HA, McGreal MJ, Thiel EC, Fine S, Erlichman C. Patients' willingness to enter clinical trials: measuring the association with perceived benefit and preference for decision participation. Soc Sci Med. 1991;32:35–42. [PubMed]
180. Weinfurt KP, Castel LD, Li Y, et al. The correlation between patient characteristics and expectations of benefit from phase I clinical trials. Cancer. 2003;98:166–175. [PubMed]
181. Horng S, Grady C. Misunderstanding in clinical research: distinguishing therapeutic misconception, therapeutic misestimation, and therapeutic optimism. IRB. 2003;25:11–16. [PubMed]
182. Miller FG. Ethical significance of ethics-related empirical research. J Natl Cancer Inst. 2002;94:1821–1822. [PubMed]
183. Lidz CW, Appelbaum PS, Grisso T, Renaud M. Therapeutic misconception and the appreciation of risks in clinical trials. Soc Sci Med. 2004;58:1689–1697. [PubMed]
184. Appelbaum PS, Lidz CW, Grisso T. Therapeutic misconception in clinical research: frequency and risk factors. IRB. 2004;26:1–8. [PubMed]
185. Dunn L, Palmer BW, Keehan M, Jeste DV, Appelbaum P. Assessment of therapeutic misconception in older schizophrenia patients using a brief instrument. Am J Psychiatry. In press. [PubMed]
186. National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research. The Belmont Report. Washington, DC: US Government Printing Office; 1978. DHEW publication OS-78-0012.
187. Nelson RM, Merz JF. Voluntariness of consent for research: an empirical and conceptual review. Med Care. 2002;40:V69–80. [PubMed]
188. Moser DJ, Arndt S, Kanz JE, et al. Coercion and informed consent in research involving prisoners. Compr Psychiatry. 2004;45:1–9. [PubMed]
189. Roberts LW. Informed consent and the capacity for voluntarism. Am J Psychiatry. 2002;159:705–712. [PubMed]
190. Dunn LB, Gordon NE. Improving informed consent and enhancing recruitment for research by understanding economic behavior. JAMA. 2005;293:609–612. [PubMed]
191. Faden R, Beauchamp T, King N. A History and Theory of Informed Consent. New York: Oxford University Press; 1986.
192. Parker LS. Ethical concerns in the research and treatment of complex disease. Trends Genet. 1995;11:520–523. [PubMed]
193. Watson M, Foster C, Eeles R, et al. Psychosocial impact of breast/ovarian (BRCA1/2) cancer-predictive genetic testing in a UK multi-centre clinical cohort. Br J Cancer. 2004;91:1787–1794. [PMC free article] [PubMed]
194. Almqvist EW, Brinkman RR, Wiggins S, Hayden MR. Psychological consequences and predictors of adverse events in the first 5 years after predictive testing for Huntington's disease. Clin Genet. 2003;64:300–309. [PubMed]
195. Babul R, Adam S, Kremer B, et al. Attitudes toward direct predictive testing for the Huntington disease gene: relevance for other adult-onset disorders: The Canadian Collaborative Group on Predictive Testing for Huntington Disease. JAMA. 1993;270:2321–2325. [PubMed]
196. Warner TD, Roberts LW, Nguyen K. Do psychiatrists understand research-related experiences, attitudes, and motivations of schizophrenia study participants? Compr Psychiatry. 2003;44:227–233. [PubMed]
197. Roberts LW, Warner TD, Brody JL. Perspectives of patients with schizophrenia and psychiatrists regarding ethically important aspects of research participation. Am J Psychiatry. 2000;157:67–74. [PubMed]
198. Verheggen FW, Nieman F, Jonkers R. Determinants of patient participation in clinical studies requiring informed consent: why patients enter a clinical trial. Patient Educ Couns. 1998;35:111–125. [PubMed]
199. Mattson ME, Curb JD, McArdle R. Participation in a clinical trial: the patients' point of view. Control Clin Trials. 1985;6:156–167. [PubMed]
200. Criscione LG, Sugarman J, Sanders L, Pisetsky DS, St Clair EW. Informed consent in a clinical trial of a novel treatment for rheumatoid arthritis. Arthritis Rheum. 2003;49:361–367. [PubMed]
201. Jaskiw GE, Blumer TE, Gutierrez-Esteinou R, Meltzer HY, Steele V, Strauss ME. Comparison of inpatients with major mental illness who do and do not consent to low-risk research. Psychiatry Res. 2003;119:183–188. [PubMed]
202. Bentley JP, Thacker PG. The influence of risk and monetary payment on the research participation decision making process. J Med Ethics. 2004;30:293–298. [PMC free article] [PubMed]
203. Dickert N, Grady C. What's the price of a research subject? approaches to payment for research participation. N Engl J Med. 1999;341:198–203. [PubMed]
204. Emanuel EJ. Ending concerns about undue inducement. J Law Med Ethics. 2004;32:100–105. [PubMed]
205. Macklin R. “Due” and “undue” inducements: on paying money to research subjects. IRB. 1981;3:1–6. [PubMed]
206. Wilkinson M, Moore A. Inducement in research. Bioethics. 1997;11:373–389. [PubMed]
207. McNeill P. Paying people to participate in research: why not? A response to Wilkinson and Moore. Bioethics. 1997;11:390–396. [PubMed]
208. Halpern SD, Karlawish JH, Casarett D, Berlin JA, Asch DA. Empirical assessment of whether moderate payments are undue or unjust inducements for participation in clinical trials. Arch Intern Med. 2004;164:801–803. [PubMed]
209. Halpern SD. Prospective preference assessment: a method to enhance the ethics and efficiency of randomized controlled trials. Control Clin Trials. 2002;23:274–288. [PubMed]
210. Bell J, Whiton J, Connelly S. Evaluation of NIH Implementation of Section 491 of the Public Health Service Act, Mandating a Program of Protection for Research Subjects. Arlington Va: James Bell Associates; 1998.
211. Hayes GJ, Hayes SC, Dykstra T. A survey of university institutional review boards: characteristics, policies, and procedures. IRB. 1995;17:1–6. [PubMed]
212. Sengupta S, Lo B. The roles and experiences of nonaffiliated and non-scientist members of institutional review boards. Acad Med. 2003;78:212–218. [PubMed]
213. Meslin EM, Lavery JV, Sutherland HJ, Till JE. Judging the ethical merit of clinical trials: what criteria do research ethics board members use? IRB. 1994;16:6–10. [PubMed]
214. Van Luijn HE, Musschenga AW, Keus RB, Robinson WM, Aaronson NK. Assessment of the risk/benefit ratio of phase II cancer clinical trials by institutional review board (IRB) members. Ann Oncol. 2002;13:1307–1313. [PubMed]
215. Candilis PJ, Lidz CW, Arnold R. The need to understand IRB deliberations. IRB. In press. [PubMed]
216. De Vries RG, Forsberg CP. What do IRBs look like? What kind of support do they receive? Account Res. 2002;9:199–216. [PubMed]
217. Shah S, Whittle A, Wilfond B, Gensler G, Wendler D. How do institutional review boards apply the federal risk and benefit standards for pediatric research? JAMA. 2004;291:476–482. [PubMed]
218. Churchill LR, Nelson DK, Henderson GE, et al. Assessing benefits in clinical research: why diversity in benefit assessment can be risky. IRB. 2003;25:1–8. [PubMed]
219. Office of the Inspector General, Department of Health and Human Services. Institutional Review Boards: A Time for Reform. Washington, DC: Office of the Inspector General, Dept of Health and Human Services; 1998.
220. Burman WJ, Reves RR, Cohn DL, Schooley RT. Breaking the camel's back: multicenter clinical trials and local institutional review boards. Ann Intern Med. 2001;134:152–157. [PubMed]
221. Paasche-Orlow MK, Taylor HA, Brancati FL. Readability standards for informed-consent forms as compared with actual readability. N Engl J Med. 2003;348:721–726. [PubMed]
222. Silverman HJ, Luce JM, Schwartz J. Protecting subjects with decisional impairment in research: the need for a multifaceted approach. Am J Respir Crit Care Med. 2004;169:10–14. [PubMed]
223. Federman D, Hannam K, Lyman Rodriguez L. Responsible Research: A Systems Approach to Protecting Research Participants. Washington, DC: Institute of Medicine, National Academies Press; 2002.
224. Stroup TS, Bredthauer E, Appelbaum PS. Use of a “Subject Advocate” in a large-scale, multi-phase clinical trial for schizophrenia: evaluation of procedures in the Clinical Antipsychotic Trials of Intervention Effectiveness (CATIE) Schizophrenia Trial. Schizophr Bull. In press.
225. Cohen BJ, McGarvey EL, Pinkerton RC, Kryzhanivska L. Willingness and competence of depressed and schizophrenic inpatients to consent to research. J Am Acad Psychiatry Law. 2004;32:134–143. [PubMed]
226. Combs DR, Adams SD, Wood TD, Basso MR, Gouvier WD. Informed consent in schizophrenia: the use of cues in the assessment of understanding. Schizophr Res. 2005;77:59–63. [PubMed]
227. Wirshing DA, Sergi MJ, Mintz J. A videotape intervention to enhance the informed consent process for medical and psychiatric treatment research. Am J Psychiatry. 2005;162:186–188. [PubMed]
228. Palmer BW, Jeste DV. Relationship of individual cognitive abilities to specific components of decisional capacity among middle-aged and older patients with schizophrenia. Schizophr Bull. In press. [PMC free article] [PubMed]
229. Koren D, Poyurovsky M, Seidman LJ, Goldsmith M, Wenger S, Klein EM. The neuropsychological basis of competence to consent in first-episode schizophrenia: a pilot metacognitive study. Biol Psychiatry. 2005;57:609–616. [PubMed]
230. Eyler LT, Mirzakhanian H, Jeste DV. A preliminary study of interactive questioning methods to assess and improve understanding of informed consent among patients with schizophrenia. Schizophr Res. 2005;75:193–198. [PubMed]
231. Prentice KJ, Gold JM, Carpenter WT. Optimistic bias in the perception of personal risk: patterns in schizophrenia. Am J Psychiatry. 2005;162:507–512. [PubMed]
232. Roberts LW, Warner TD, Anderson CT, Smithpeter MV, Rogers MK. Schizophrenia research participants' responses to protocol safeguards: recruitment, consent, and debriefing. Schizophr Res. 2004;67:283–291. [PubMed]
233. Roberts LW, Warner TD, Brody JL, Nguyen K, Roberts BB. What is ethically important in clinical research? a preliminary study of attitudes of 73 psychiatric faculty and residents. Schizophr Bull. 2003;29:607–613. [PubMed]
234. Osborn DP, Fulford KW. Psychiatric research: what ethical concerns do LRECs encounter? a postal survey. Local research ethics committees. J Med Ethics. 2003;29:55–56. [PMC free article] [PubMed]

Articles from Schizophrenia Bulletin are provided here courtesy of Oxford University Press